Thursday, October 18, 2012

Adrienne Rich and Monique Wittig (or, Chloë and Olivia, the sequel)

Like Woolf and Cixous, both Rich and Wittig are first and foremost creative writers -- Rich a poet, Wittig a French-language novelist -- who are also feminist activists and theorists. Unlike Cixous and Woolf, though, Rich and Wittig don't write theory in a way that seems stylistically continuous with fiction or poetry. This isn't to say that they don't write movingly or take advantage of particular figurative and rhetorical devices in their prose--see Rich's rather stunning description of "the queasy strobe light" of compulsory heterosexuality that "flickers across and distorts our lives," for example (1607) -- yet it does seem fair to say that their writing violates fewer of the conventional norms for discursive prose: we'll find no imaginary Manx cats, no enthusiastic evocations of masturbation, no "pwetty eyes" (1958). Since we've discussed the value of these literary strategies for theory while looking at Woolf and Cixous, one overall question for us on Friday would be about the relative and tactical pros and cons of abandoning such stylistic experiments.


Adrienne Rich, "Compulsory Heterosexuality and Lesbian Existence"
Like Johnson, both Rich and Wittig give us, in their extensive footnotes, a sense of how wide-ranging and various the projects of feminist and queer scholarship had become by the early '80s: the graduates of Newnham and Girton had by this time more than taken up the suggestions for future research made by Woolf in Room.

Adrienne Rich
Unlike Johnson, though -- remember that her essay was written later, in 1998 -- both Wittig and especially Rich write at a moment when the women's movement and, a fortiori, the gay rights movement felt the gains made since The Feminine Mystique (1963) to be far from secure. The late '70s had seen Anita Bryant gain a national audience for her "Save Our Children" campaign, which sought to save children not from hunger or poor schools but from gays with civil rights. ("If homosexuals are allowed civil rights, then so would [sic] prostitutes, or thieves, or anyone else" -- see the video below; skip to a minute or so in for the original footage of Bryant). The Equal Rights Amendment (see Lorde 119) was dead in the water by 1981, after what had seemed like its nearly inevitable ratification in the previous decade. Ronald Reagan had won the 1980 presidential election on a "family values" platform that most feminists and gays felt to be inimical to their causes.



Rich's essay has the ambitious goal of contextualizing female heterosexuality within an array of social, political, and economic practices, ranging from sex trafficking to advertising to pornography to workplace harassment and unequal pay. Foucault argues that "power is everywhere; not because it embraces everything, but because it comes from everywhere" (93). Rich's essay at once tries to enumerate a set of under-observed sources of male and heterosexual, and (thereby) to make possible a strategy within the feminist movement to resist and transform these sources. This strategy of naming unspoken things is, of course, also Friedan's; Rich borrows a formulation of it--I think, though the footnote placement is odd--from Kathleen Barry, Female Sexual Slavery:
Until we name the practice, give conceptual definition and form to it, illustrate its life over time and in space, those who are its most obvious victims will also not be able to name it or define their experience. (quoted N 1600)
We should think, then, about the usefulness (and limitations) of some of Rich's chosen terms. Two of her major innovations in this regard are "lesbian existence" and "lesbian continuum." Rich prefers "lesbian existence" to "lesbianism," she says, because the latter "a clinical and limiting ring" (1603). What advantages does she see in the term "lesbian existence"? Do these seem convincing to you?

"Lesbian continuum," Rich writes, is meant to suggest "a range...of woman-identified experience," including "forms of primary intensity" that don't arise from sexual acts between women (1603-4). Rich's tactic here, we might say, is to loosen the conceptual tie between "lesbian" and any particular kind of sexual aim or object. Again, what are the gains of this strategy? (We should be sure to get clear about the meaning of "woman-identified" and "male-identified" in this context as well--we rather hurried past these important terms while discussing Lorde).

Considering more broadly the place of sexuality in Rich's essay, we might compare her description of the "erotic in female terms" to Cixous's. Here's Rich:
...as we delineate a lesbian continuum, we begin to discover the erotic in female terms: as that which is unconfined to any single part of the body or solely to the body itself; as an energy not only diffuse but, as Audre Lorde has described it, omnipresent in "the sharing of joy, whether physical, emotional, psychic," and in the sharing of work; as the empowering joy which "makes us less willing to accet powerlessness..." (1604)
And here's a similar moment from "The Laugh of the Medusa":
I have been amazed more than once by a description a woman gave me of a world all her own which she had been secretly haunting since early childhood. A world of searching, the elaboration of knowledge on the basis of a systematic experimentation with the bodily functions, a passionate and precise interrogation of her ertogeneity. This practice, extraordinarily rich and inventive, in particular as concerns masturbation, is prolonged or accompanied by a production of forms, a veritable aesthetic activity, each stage of rapture inscribing a resonant vision, a composition, something beautiful. (1943)
These moments are similar in that both Rich and Cixous object, as they elsewhere in their essays, to a typically male imagining of sexuality as fetishistically localized in the genitals; they see female eroticism as more diffuse, more "polymorphous" (to use Freud's term, though with a different value). What are the important differences between these passages, though, in terms of emphasis and style? What different conclusions do Rich and Cixous draw from fundamentally similar ideas about a distinctively feminine sexuality?

Sexual violence: Finally, Rich brings into the foreground the issue of sexual violence between men and women, in the forms of forced prostitution, sexual abuse, rape, and harassment.

While we haven't focused on these issues as of yet, it's worth recalling here that the place of sadism and masochism in sexual behavior were already problems for Freud in The Three Essays: sadism and masochism are "the most common and the most significant of all the perversions" (23), and they "occupy a special position among the perversions, since the contrast between activity and passivity which lies behind them is among the universal characteristics of sexual life" (25). What's striking here is that, rather as Freud saw homosexuality as a special kind of preference but also a latent potential within every person ("original bisexuality"), here he seems unable to decide whether sadism and masochism are special kinds of sexuality or tendencies inherent to all sexuality whatsoever.

Drawing on the scholarship of Catherine MacKinnon, Rich calls into question the distinctions between (heterosexual) sex and violence underlying contemporary studies of rape (see 1598-99). Whereas Freud observes the pervasiveness of an aggressive component to sexual behavior, which he sees as more often (though not exclusively) characteristic of men than of women, Rich is interested in the concrete effects of male sexuality as a form of socially sanctioned aggression. Against those who would see rape as violence and intercourse as sexuality, Rich argues (following MacKinnon) that perhaps all intercourse is rape, that it's difficult to tell the difference between them.

Compulsion, Desire, Violence, Consent: This brings us to what is perhaps the central raised by Rich's argument: what does she mean by saying that heterosexuality is "compulsory," that women live "in the absence of choice" (1609) in the matter? Clearly, Rich can't mean that no women can choose to have sex with other women, or that no women are able to love other women. It does sound here, though, as if she's saying that no woman can choose to be heterosexual. Is that indeed her argument?

Here's a thought experiment that might help us sort out her claim: You crave almond butter. You go to the grocery store to find no almond butter, but only a shelf full of Skippy peanut butter -- creamy, not chunky. It costs $50 per jar. You ask the store manager if there's any almond butter, or even some other kind of peanut butter--with a bit less sugar, perhaps. No luck. You can, though, buy a bag of unshelled almonds for $1000, and grind them into almond butter yourself. Your choice. Or is it? What, in other words, are the conditions of possibility for choice, or for consent?

Monique Wittig, "One is Not Born a Woman"

Though deeply critical of the naturalization of gender roles in the text of Marx and in Marxist practice, Wittig's "One is Not Born a Woman" makes an argument about women patterned on Marx's argument about the proletariat (or working-class): Just as the proletariat must become conscious of itself as a class in order to bring about a classless society, so must women become conscious of themselves as a (non-natural, socially constructed) class in order to bring about a sexless society--a society without "men" or "women":

What does "feminist" mean? Feminist is formed with the word "femme," "woman," and means: someone who fights for women as a class and for the disappearance of this class. (1909)
Yet Wittig notes that many feminists don't understand feminism in this way in practice: "For many others it means someone who fights for woman and her defense--for the myth, then, and its reenforcement" (1909). We've seen Barbara Johnson articulate a version of the impasse that Wittig struggles with here:
...deconstruction introduces a fissure between "woman" as a concept that can never be a proper name for all women and "feminism" as a movement that must -- but cannot -- consider "woman" as an epistemological ground for action. (Johnson, 7)
Feminism requires some concept of "woman," but is also dedicated to changing the entrenched and stereotyped versions of that concept. Wittig goes a step further in seeking not a change but an end to the concept. In doing so, she asserts that "the capacity to give birth (biology)" should not be seen to define women, because this "naturalize[s] history" (1907), mistakes the made for the given. This places her at odds with varieties of feminism that seek to define woman or femininity affirmatively, or to use female specificity as a psychological or political resource:
The refusal to become (or to remain) heterosexual always meant to refuse to become a man or a woman, consciously or not. For a lesbian this goes further than the refusal of the role "woman." It is the refusal of the economic, ideological, and political power of a man. This, we lesbians, and nonlesbians as well, knew before the beginning of the lesbian and feminist movement. However, as Andrea Dworkin emphasizes, many lesbians recently "have increasingly tried to transform the very ideology that has enslaved us into a dynamic, religious, psychologically compelling celebration of female biological potential. Thus, some avenues of the feminist and lesbian movement lead us back to the myth of woman which was created by men especially for us, and with it we sink back into a natural group. (1909-10) 
We might wonder, here, how Wittig and Cixous would respond to each other, given that Cixous sometimes does indeed celebrate a specifically feminine sexuality:

Bring the other to life. Women know how to live detachment; giving birth is neither losing nor increasing. It's adding to life an other. Am I dreaming? Am I mis-recognizing? You, the defenders of "theory," the sacrosanct yes-men of Concept, enthroners of the phallus (but not of the penis): Once more you'll say that all this smacks of "idealism," or what's worse, you'll splutter that I'm a "mystic." (Cixous, 1957)
Is Wittig one of the "yes-men of the Concept"? Is Cixous a mystic? How might we understand the (apparent?) conflict between their feminisms?

For Wittig, the category that escapes the historical legacy of sexism and heterosexism embedded in the categories of "man" and "woman" is "lesbian":
Lesbian is the only concept I know of which is beyond the categories of sex (woman and man), because the designated subject (lesbian) is not a woman, either economically, or politically, or ideologically. (1912)
I don't want to overplay the differences and conflicts among the theories of Cixous, Rich, and Wittig: surely they have a great deal of common ground, and would agree about many practical matters of social and political reform. Yet in this last quote, Wittig, whose arguments are in some ways so resonant with those of Rich, would seem to be at odds with her: if for Rich a lesbian is the quintessentially woman-identified woman, it seems that for Wittig, "lesbian" is politically valuable as a category precisely for not being identified with woman, as she says emphatically at the end of "The Straight Mind": "Lesbians are not women" (32). Before deciding which of these positions you agree with, you should think about the potential uses and values of each.

As for Rich, the place of sexuality in Wittig's theory is again a point of interest: she defines lesbians by opposition to social and political forms of oppression, and not primarily in terms of sexual desire.

Another point of contact with our earlier readings comes in Wittig's claim that "equality in difference" is an illogical principle (and note that she seems to echo here the "separate but equal" language of Brown vs. The Board of Education). Obviously, this places her in emphatic disagreement with writers like Lorde and Cixous who see difference as a value in itself; see too Johnson's discussion (borrowing from Joan Scott) of the conflicts between and equality (Johnson, 5).

"The Straight Mind"
Monique Wittig
In this essay, Wittig looks back at the linguistic turn in the human sciences, which happened earliest and most emphatically in France, following Saussure, and slowly spread abroad in the second half of the 20th century. Wittig's title for this essay echoes the structuralist anthropologist Claude Lévi-Strauss's The Savage Mind (La Pensée sauvage) (see her page 27).

Wittig sees structuralism, including Lévi-Strauss and Lacan, as faulty first of all because it (like Saussurean linguistics, which studies languages as fixed and not changing structures) it is ahistorical. This criticism is, to a point, typical of the varied schools of thought sometimes categorized as "poststructural," of which Derrida and Foucault are usually taken to be exemplary. Indeed, Derrida articulates his post-structural theory precisely through a critique of the ahistoricity of Lévi-Strauss in "Structure, Sign and Play in the Human Sciences" (in Derrida's Writing and Difference).

Where Derrida sees not enough difference in structuralism, a failure to take account of temporal difference, Wittig again wishes to do away with difference altogether. Her motivations for this theoretical move lie in the history of oppression that conceptual differences (especially binaries) have undergirded--you'll think back on Dora, no doubt, as you read her critique of psychoanalysis (23ff.).

Wittig's ideas about language as having "material" consequences might recall Foucault's discussion of discourse and power: do you see substantial overlap between these two thinkers? Are there important differences between them that you would point to?

There's a moment at the end of Wittig's essay that seems as important as it is easy to overlook:
...let us say that we break off the heterosexual contract.
     So, this is what lesbians say everywhere in this country and in some others, if not with theories at least through their social practice, whose repercussions upon straight culture and society are still unenvisionable. (32)
 The interesting suggestion here is that social practices speak, even if not yet articulately. We might think back here to Woolf's decision, in Room, to tell stories (about a walk on campus, a luncheon, a dinner) before articulating theories, or to Cixous's description of women's speech as expressive not just of ideas but of drives. We often think of theory as avant-garde, as articulating ideas that practice will need to catch up with, yet Wittig reverses that common conception. Since she doesn't provide examples of these practices, can you imagine what she might have in mind?

We'll continue to think about the relation of practice and theory later this semester -- next week, to begin with, as we turn to the work of Judith Butler.

9 comments:

  1. Reading “One is Not Born a Woman” was an incredibly striking experience because it related to a lot of feminist theories that I’ve encountered in the past. When Wittig states, “women’s oppression destroys the idea that women are a ‘natural group’.” Stating, “one is not born, but becomes a woman” is an idea that comes up constantly in the theory of Intersectionality. Intersectionality theory posits that everyone has unique experiences based on all their different identities and different forms of oppression. This relates when Wittig states that women are “a racial group of a special kind.” It reminds me greatly of how intersectionality creates a whole new category based on oppression. Therefore you are your own category of person if you are an African American, Lesbian, Female.
    I also liked the idea of women’s oppression being “biological as well as historical.” This connects to the next part of the article where Wittig states that “men are biologically inferior to women.” This concept always boggles me because it seems as though women should be worshipped for their ability to create life. This is also something I would enjoy going over further in either this course or another gender course in the future.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. It's important to distinguish two quite separate moments in your account of Wittig's argument. It's just right to suggest that intersectionality theory is a useful framework within which to understand Wittig (and Rich and Lorde and Johnson, I think): all of these theorists are interested in the ways in which multiple axes of difference (gender, sexuality, age, race, class) constitute particular subjects.

      For Wittig, though, it's also the case any attempt to ground such distinctions in biology is misleading, a way of "naturalizing" what is in fact (on Wittig's view) entirely a matter of history. When Wittig refers to "lesbian-feminists" who see "women's oppression as _biological as well as_ historical" (1907), she does so to _critique_ this view, not to support it. The same is true for lesbian feminists--Andrea Dworkin is the case in point--who assert that "men are biologically inferior to women" (1907). Wittig sees these naturalizing arguments as only mirror images of the sort of argument that grounds the sociopolitical dominance of men in biology: "By doing this, by admitting that there is a 'natural' division between women and men, we naturalize history, we assume that 'men' and 'women' have always existed and will always exist" (1907). Because such arguments for women's biological superiority only mirror the male vision of the argument, they are on Wittig's view an insufficient response, a reflex rather than a critical innovation. The sexes are historically constituted classes, and her hope is that a progressive history will erase these classes (men and women) altogether. This is a utopian but not, perhaps -- see Amanda Ely's comment below -- an unimaginable state of society.

      Delete
  2. While reading "One Is Not Born a Woman," I found Monique Wittig's aversion to the term "woman" intriguing, especially in light of her acceptance - even embracement - of her definition by the term "lesbian." For Wittig, then, the frustration at the designation of her gender is not due to its identity as a word, which can be seen as a product of social constructs. If she objected to the term "woman" because it was oppositional to "man" or because she felt it was an unnecessary signifier, a similar objection to being called a lesbian would exist. It is possible that I do not understand Wittig's point of view simply because I have not faced the same gender discriminations in my lifetime, but I disagree with her definition of "woman." The distinctions between genders may be oppositional, but only in diction; I am not upset by the descriptor "green" because it contrasts with "red", when both are used to portray apples. Women are not, however, as easily defined as pieces of fruit; does the difference between men and women lay in childbearing ability, muscle mass, neurological pathways, or a mental state?

    ReplyDelete
  3. I found Wittig's idea of a sexless society really interesting. Instead of arguing that women should work harder or that they just need the opportunity to distinguish themselves or that they should have the same rights as men, she says that we need to get rid of the categories of man and woman altogether. At one point, she says that the concepts of man and woman "are political categories and not natural givens" (1909). This is interesting, because she seems to be saying that men and women's biological differences are not a very important factor in gender inequality and that the suppression of women has more to do with social constructs.
    This also reminded me of something we recently read about in one my sociology course. There is an Asian society called the Lahu who traditionally do not distinguish between men and women. Men and women are viewed as essentially the same, with the same capabilities and responsibilities. They are two halves of a complete whole. They compare this to a pair of chopsticks, where each side is essentially the same but they can only fulfill their purpose if they are put together. All their households and leadership roles are traditionally headed by a man and woman pair with equal power. This concept seems to have worked in this society, so perhaps Wittig was on to something.

    ReplyDelete
  4. I found these readings very interesting. The first, "One is Nor Born a Women", was a bit confusing. I dont quite understand her argument that lesbians are not women. I think she is talking about how these categories of sex, men and women, are created in society and lesbians have a different category. She also talks about how everyone needs to be an individual yet a member of a class. I did not understand how she explained this contrast. I really enjoyed Rich's piece because she talked about a lot of topics I am interested in. Her main point, which I have wondered myself, is why do we frame everything in reference to heterosexuality? Why do we assume everyone is heterosexual? Why is heterosexuality our default and everything we know based on that paradigm?
    I was really interested in the different arguments and topics she discussed. Initially, I think i was reading this and thinking about it in general terms, about the issues and thinking o my opinions, but i was not thinking about it in terms of how this effects lesbians. And this is precisely her point - we do not think about these issues in terms of homosexuality. I was thinking about how I am interested in pornography and the consequences it has. Her mentioning of how men want to be in control reminds me of my internship. We do not immediately relate these issues to lesbians - our default is heterosexuality. I thought she brought up great questions and touched on many important issues.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. This comment has been removed by the author.

      Delete
    2. Wittig is indeed a bit difficult to follow--because compressed, dense, allusive--on the question of the relation between "class consciousness" and "subjectivity" within Marxist feminism. Yet the difficulty is by no means just a matter of her writing--it's a matter of what's difficult to _think_ simply by virtue of the complexity of lived experience. Wittig's account of the relation between individual and class is dialectical in the best sense:

      "This real necessity for everyone to exist as an individual, as well as a member of a class, is perhaps the first condition for the accomplishment of a revolution, without which there can be no real fight or transformation. But the opposite is also true; without class and class consciousness there are no real subjects, only alienated individuals. For women to answer the question of the individual subject in materialist terms is first to show, as the lesbians and feminists did, that supposedly "subjective," "individual," "private" problems are in fact social problems, class problems; that sexuality is not for women an individual and subjective expression, but a social institution of violence" (1912).

      This is confusing to the extent, perhaps, that life as a gendered subject is confusing. Wittig faults Marxism (I'll riskily paraphrase) for regarding subjectivity as a product of oppression and not as a producer of the overthrow of oppression; it's hard to find a place for the self in "class consciousness," she suggests. Yet atomistic individualism is no viable alternative; what, after all, is a subject that understands herself as entirely autonomous, somehow untouched by the historically produced inequalities of sex? A (feminist) subject, in other words, has to respect both her own agency _and_ be aware of the class structure that that agency should seek to transform and, ultimately, erase. An historically powerful individual must be aware of, but not confined by, her belonging to an historically constituted class.

      I'm glad you were interested in Rich's essay; it is indeed powerful in its positing of an alternative to heterosexual presumption, a "tactical" essay, in the hopeful Foucauldian sense, that suggests radically different possibilities within the discourse of sexuality.

      Delete
  5. As usual, I'm going to focus on a very small part of the material we actually read (and went over) for today's class, and instead of encompassing more, tell an unnecessary anecdote that explains my (very humble) opinion:
    Although I usually try to repress any thoughts of doing actual work when I hang out with my friends, today I felt that Adrienne Rich would be the perfect lunch-time topic. I should probably preface this by saying that I'm "that friend" that likes to go for shock value, people are never really sure where I'm going with a conversation and have learned that they probably shouldn't be surprised by things that I say... but usually they still are. Anyway, we were at lunch, and I went ahead and told them that, according to a famous, brilliant theorist that we were reading in class, we were actually lesbians. They gave me a collective deadpan stare, and Chrissy, who is very happily in a heterosexual relationship rolled her eyes and said "what are you even talking about?"
    Adrienne Rich, obviously I was talking about Adrienne Rich. I pulled out Norton, as large as it is, and explained the Lesbian Continuum. I moved on to say that relationships between women--erotic or not--inherently lead to a special female bond, that Rich would explain as being a form of Lesbianism, something men will never understand because they simply are not women. This got my four best female friends talking. Of course bonds between women are closer than bonds between men--not that you can't have a serious bromance, but women certainly are much more passionate with other women than men are with other men. We discussed our own discourse; calling each other beautiful, making sure to give compliments when they are due, and saying "love you" when we all settle into bed and say goodnight. It's more than that though, we also cuddle with each other, nap in the same bed, help each other get dressed, and it's all completely normal. We could not imagine a situation where men would be as close as the five of us are. We also discussed the fact that women are much more aware of other women than men are of other men--if you ask a guy what another guy looks like, he'll give you the bare minimum, but if you ask a woman what another woman looks like, she can usually rattle off a string of details and give an excellent description, simply because we pay attention to those kinds of things in each other. For these reason, it is safe to say that I think that Rich is absolutely right about the idea of all female relationships being a form of lesbianism, because I do believe that the female bond is something very special, and extends beyond just simple friendship.
    This does make things difficult for those who are actually lesbians in the sense that they enjoy having intercourse with other women. I find it problematic that we, as straight women, could be kind of stealing their title, because that takes away something that they should be able to specifically own. I'm not quite sure how this could be changed, but it is certainly all very interesting to think about.

    ReplyDelete
    Replies
    1. Any time critical theory makes its way to the lunch table, I feel like our class has accomplished something more than theoretical.

      And the kinds of experience you're talking about here are of course what underlie theory in the first place. It's striking, assuming your own experience is representative, how much less troubled or bounded female friendships are by homophobia than male ones. I wonder about the _history_ of that experience, about the extent to which it has changed over the past few decades, as (and this is a speculative and very broad brush I'm painting with...) expanding personal opportunities have freed up women's attention for each other, and away from concentration on marriage and relationships with men (Rich might say, as they've become less "male-identified").

      As for "bromance," probably not in the O.E.D. just yet, I'm never sure if it's a way to name a male friendship that acknowledges its departure from straightness, or a more defensive attempt to find a word that designates the friendship as non-gay; it may be useful because it can do both kinds of work?

      Delete