—Foucault, History of Sexuality, vol. I, p. 69
Herbert Marcuse [in Eros and Civilization (1955)] interpreted the contemporary phenomena of a sexual liberation that is controlled, socially regulated, and at the same time commercialized and administered, as "repressive desublimation." This analysis holds open the perspective of a liberating desublimation. Foucault starts from the quite similar phenomenon of a sexuality that has been disqualified, reduced to a medium of control, and stripped of all eroticism--but he sees in it the telos, the revealed secret of sexual liberation.
—Jürgen Habermas, The Philosophical Discourse of Modernity (1985; trans. 1987), p. 291
What are norms? (truth, power, normality, normativity)
Foucault argues that the real secret of sexuality is its
harnessing of the truth about the self to coercive forms of power.
This is not, of course, what the construction of sex as a
secret buried within the self was meant, by powers that are “intentional and
nonsubjective,” to reveal.
Foucault wants to show how the search for
sex as an inner, private truth is precisely a diversion from more efficacious
forms of knowing and doing.
Yet what if Foucault himself has a secret? This is the claim
of Jürgen Habermas, whose understanding of Foucault in the passage above we
might relate to Sedgwick’s discussion of “paranoid” theories (which isn’t to
say that Sedgwick would agree with Habermas altogether). Sedgwick notices that
such theories keep exposing over and over again the same unhappy truths, and
this is what Habermas points out above: the “secret” that Foucault himself
reveals is always the same, always the coercive normalization enacted upon
bodies by truth-power.
For Habermas, though, the important secret in Foucault’s
critique lies one level deeper than this. He thinks what lies
hidden—unexamined, unexplained—in Foucault’s writing is the normative basis of
Foucault’s own critique of norms. In other words, Foucault’s writing exposes
the forms of power exerted upon children, homosexuals, prisoners, and others through
coercive regimes of truth. Yet his reasons for focusing his (and our) energies
on these gestures of exposure, and
for caring about them, must themselves be normative, must depend on true
beliefs about what is just and good.
Ideas about what is just and good, about what should be done, what we should do, are
called norms.
Are norms true and reasonable, or are they essentially
coercive, a way to exert power masked as truth?
It’s on this latter question that many of the authors we’re
reading this week disagree. They argue in the wake of a debate between Foucault
and Habermas on this question. The basic sticking point of their conflict is
about the relation of truth and power in norms.
For Foucault, truth and power are always coextensive. What
we do in arriving at norms is to normalize, to create standards that will be
oppressive in proportion as one deviates from them.
For Habermas, as for much of the Enlightenment tradition that
Foucault critiques, norms are truth but not power. That is, norms should be a form of rational,
consensually agreed upon truth. We need norms as rational guidelines for the
just use of power, and for the critique of unjust power. Habermas is not naïve about
the extent to which norms do not always function this way in practice, nor is
he an essentialist about what the proper norms for a group of persons are—such
norms have to be arrived at through public debate and democratic political
processes. But he would insist that norms can be rational, and so in the face
of a situation in which we find that existing norms are functioning unjustly,
as in the exclusion of gay people from certain civil rights or the unequal
compensation of women for their work, then what we need are better norms.
A Foucauldian argument might insist that the search for
“better norms” is naïve and dangerous to the extent that it imagines that norms
can ever be divested of coercive power. That ideal of truth without power is
bound to collapse into ideology, a truth whose false universality will function
for the benefit of some and to the detriment of others. We should give up on
the idea of norms altogether.
Amanda Anderson, "Debatable Performances"
Amanda Anderson |
Brown elaborates the Foucauldian (also Nietzschean) critique
of truth as a form of power in her essay, but she’s not merely concerned to
critique this relationship: rather, she’s urging feminists to embrace the
inseparability of truth and power. Why, and how?
Anderson, whose essay is a virtuoso example of exposition
and critique, will make a case against Butler for the political usefulness of
what she calls “evaluative norms,” as distinct from the “normalizing norms”
focused on in the Foucauldian tradition. What does Anderson mean by these
terms, and why does she believe that evaluative norms are politically valuable and
not just coercive?
Anderson will also, of course, argue that Butler’s theory is
more useful for the formation of evaluative norms than either Butler or Benhabib admit. Anderson advances
this part of her argument through a critique of Benhabib’s discussion of S/M,
and a discussion of the “disidentification” valued—rightly, says Anderson—by
Butler. Here, we see a continuation of last week’s discussion of identity
politics. Why is disidentification
politically valuable, on Anderson’s account?
Berlant and Warner, "Sex in Public"
Lauren Berlant |
Michael Warner |
Gay marriage as example: Michael Warner and Andrew Sullivan
In many ways, Warner and Berlant are aligned with Butler’s
critique of normalization. In "The Politics of Homosexuality" (1993), which Warner has called “the most
influential gay essay of the ’90s” (TwN
52), the conservative British (now American) gay journalist Andrew Sullivan
argued that gay people did and should aspire to normality, understood broadly
as integration into mainstream politics and culture, and that a more just
extension of political freedoms and rights, including marriage, would enable
them to achieve this. Sullivan expanded the article into a book, Virtually Normal (1995).
Andrew Sullivan |
Why would a gay man argue against gay marriage?
Warner notes, first, that this question wouldn't have felt rhetorical before the '90s; from the point of view of earlier decades, in fact, it's strange that marriage has become a kind of holy grail in the quest for gay rights. Queer politics in the post-Stonewall decades, the '70s and '80s, had been more broadly critical of norms--we've seen examples of this tradition in Foucault, Butler, and Rubin among others. This tradition was formed in response to discrimination against queer persons, and not just (more narrowly) against monogamous queer couples. Warner sees political value in the less restricted, more fluid formation of intimacies, sexual and other, that was characteristic especially of gay male culture during these decades and into the present. This aspect of queer culture has been devalued as merely "promiscuous"; Warner often calls it "world-making," in recognition of how essential sexually oriented subcultures have been to queer socialization and politics.
Earlier queer politics had been critical of marriage as a heterosexual institution that gave married straight people privileged access to social goods not obviously tied to sex or sexuality: tax breaks, health insurance, joint checking accounts and so forth (the list is fairly long). One way to overcome these inequalities is, of course, to grant queer people the right to marry. Yet Warner sees this as a provisional solution at best, and one that still problematically links sexuality to aspects of citizenship that should have nothing to do with it. Marriage, he writes, “sanctifies some couples [whether gay or straight] at the expense of others. It is selective legitimacy. … Marriage, in short, discriminates” (TwN, 82). He believes that a conscientious argument for gay marriage has to see the attainment of marriage rights not as a final goal, but rather as one step of a broader program of divorcing the state from any differential treatment of persons according to (non-coercive) sexual behavior. This program, writes Warner,
would have to say that marriage is a desirable goal only insofar as we can also extend health care, tax reform, rights of intimate association extending to immigration, recognition for joint parenting, and other entitlements currently yoked to marital status. It would have to say that marriage is desirable only insofar as we can eliminate adultery laws and other status-discriminatory regulations for sexuality. It might well also involve making available other statuses, such as expanded domestic partnership, concubinage, or something like PACS for property-sharing households, all available both to straight and gay people alike. (TwN 146)
It's important to see here that while Warner wants the state to have no involvement with sexuality, this is not at all the same as saying that sexuality should not be political--in fact, sexuality must have political and public effects if the state's relation to it is to be changed. Of course, probably only a straight male could be oblivious to the public effects that gender and sexuality already do have. (The "closet," as described by Eve Sedgwick, is a potent figure of how tacit heterosexual privilege shapes the public lives of queer people in ways often invisible to straight people). There's no choice about whether sex will be public; the choices concern how it will be so.
"Many of those who hang out on Christopher Street--typically young, queer, and African-American--couldn't possibly afford to live there" (N 2613). This photo is from a 2006 New York Times article about black and Latino youths who come to Christopher Street from outlying areas. |
Civil society: publicness without the state
Habermas's public sphere is formed in the 17th and 18th centuries, culminating in the American and French Revolutions, by the middle classes in opposition to the aristocratically-controlled state. It includes the journals, newspapers, learned societies and universities that became during these centuries, for the first time, forums for cultural and, increasingly, for political argument. Yet it also includes, crucially, the family, important in the first instance as the entity through which "private" property was transmitted independently of the state. The collectivity of economically defined families was the locus of privacy from which persons could come into a public sphere not synonymous with the state: this was civil rather than political society. And so Habermas defines the public sphere as "the sphere of private people come together as a public." Warner gives the thought more pith: "The public in this new sense...was no longer opposed to the private. It was private" (Publics and Counterpublics, 47; cf. N 2609).
Of course, it didn't stay that way. Think of the role played in the American Revolution by, for example, Thomas Paine's pamphlet Common Sense. It's significant that in that pamphlet, Paine imagines the British government as an abusive father, violating its natural relationship to its colonial family in America. Here, the family is not the opposite of the state, but the standard by which it is judged. As the public sphere came to have political power, so too did the bourgeois family acquire greater normative force.
"Naked, smiling, and just off-white, Time's divine Frankenstein aims to organize hegemonic optimism about citizenship and the national future" (N 2601). |
But for Habermas, this is a betrayal of the public sphere's potential, not a sign that the public sphere was a tainted or interested or falsely universal idea from the start.
Speaking, Moving, Acting in Public: Bodies in the Public Sphere
It is no accident that ACT UP was founded by a playwright, since its politics was essentially theatrical: a fantastic display of rhetorical pique and visual brilliance. It became a national media hit, but eventually its lines became familiar and the audience's attention wavered, New shows have taken its place and will continue to do so - but they will always be constrained by their essential nature, which is performance, not persuasion.
—Andrew Sullivan, "The Politics of Homosexuality" (1993)
I'm tempted to say, reductively but in the hope that it will be useful, that Warner and Berlant take up and critique Habermas's concept of the public sphere by insisting that we imagine it more fully than does Habermas himself--not merely as an arena for reasoned speech, but as an arena for speaking bodies. Here's Warner's version of this idea:
In The Structural Transformation of the Public Sphere, Habermas speaks of “people’s public use of their reason.” But what counts as a use of reason? In later works, he has put forward a highly idealized account of argumentative dialogue. But movements around gender sexuality seek to transform fundamental styles of embodiment, identity, and social relations—including their unconscious manifestations, the vision of the good life embedded in them, and tha habitus by which people continue to understand their selves or bodies as public or private. … The ability to bracket one’s embodiment and status is not simply what Habermas calls making public use of one’s reason; it is a strategy of distinction, profoundly linked to education and to dominant forms of masculinity. (Warner, "Public and Private," in Publics and Counterpublics, p. 51)
Protestors at the office of House Speaker John Boehner, Tuesday, November 27, 2012 |
Sullivan, in the epigraph above, is suggesting that theater and politics make strange bedfellows, and he wishes they'd just get a room. That is, keep the "performances" of queer sexuality private, so that "persuasion" can do its respectable, unsexy work in the public sphere--perhaps in a three-piece grey suit and a tastefully unobtrusive tie.
Berlant and Warner seek to contest this segregation of performance and persuasion; they see all the world, bedrooms and closets included, as a stage. But this means for them not, as in the hermeneutics of suspicion, that politics is always just irrational power masquerading as truth and justice. It is rather, perhaps, a stage we can get beyond only by thoughtfully acting out our intimacies in different ways, until the political regulation of those intimacies becomes more equitable. And this even, perhaps especially, when it requires changing rationally, viscerally our sense of how what's inside us should come out--changing each other's sense of what makes us sick.
Erotic vomiting, anyone?
I enjoyed this reading. An interesting concept that I liked was that we have old family values that influence our politics. Traditional family values and beliefs have shaped our politics and benefit one group over another. They favor heterosexual norms and values. It privatizes citizenship and sex. The author gives examples of laws protecting children, financial reforms for married couples, and the denial of funding for sexually explicit material. This just creates an environment and atmosphere that marginalizes a group. Our politics are based around one group's ideas and anything that deviates from that is viewed as wrong. I also found it interesting that when heterosexual people engage in "queer culture" they feel like they cannot talk about it. In order to not feel like perverts they have to talk to gay friends they know and "make us into a queer culture" (2614).
ReplyDeleteSo the whole erotic vomiting thing. Very different. I have never heard of anything like that. I have heard of fetishes with urine and feces but vomit is new. I thought it was interesting how the author was not judging what was going on; he did not give his opinion. He looked at the situation from a different way discussing how the scene was intimate and a display of control, abandon,trust,violation. These terms I think are easier to relate to sex. You trust the other person, abandon yourself, have or give away control. We just don't relate these to vomiting.
One aspect I found to be rather interesting about Sex in Public is the fact that sex and privacy in heteronormative culture versus the queer community. In the heteronormative culture, it seems that since sex is not private in the sense that we are constantly discussing people’s romances or intimate matters, it represented Foucault’s theories on how discourse is repressive. One example of this is found in heterosexual couples therapy. We perpetuate this idea of what relationships are supposed to be like, and when these couples “mess up” or fail in their relationship because they don’t adhere to the norm, it becomes an example for the rest of us on how not to have a relationship, and thus perpetuates the norm. We “air out their bad laundry” in front of everyone. We repress the infinite potentials a relationship can be defined as because we have these examples of what a relationship should or should not be. Like in Foucault’s argument, discussing intimate details defines and represses people’s identities and sexualities.
ReplyDeleteIn the queer community on the other hand, there is more inclusivity of various types of sexualities and identities. There is a plethora of publics of opinion culture and privatized forms, which allows people to be more accepting and more private and intimate. People in the queer community don’t always have to define their identity, actions, or sexuality in order to adhere to a norm; they don’t have to discuss it in a manner where they are being scrutinized, therefore it remains private.